Eskridge and Baer have written The Supreme Court's Deference Continuum, An Empirical Analysis (Chevron to Hamdan), forthcoming in the Georgetown Law Journal. The Abstract is below the fold.
Eskridge and Baer conducted an empirical
study of all 1014 Supreme Court cases between 1984 and 2006 (inclusive)
in which an agency interpretation of a statute was at issue. Each case
was coded for 156 variables. This article, presented in preliminary
form as the 2007 Ryan Lecture at the Georgetown University Law Center,
will be the first comprehensive empirical analysis of the Supreme
Court's actual practice in agency interpretation cases. The study was
motivated by academic debates about how extensive the Supreme Court's
“Chevron Revolution” has been and ought to be, debates typically
conducted without any systematic grounding in the Court's actual
practice.
There
are dozens of descriptive contributions the article tries to make.
Consider three that illuminate larger doctrinal debates within the
Court and among commentators.
First, the data demonstrate
that the academic obsession with Chevron is doctrinally misguided, at
least as regards Supreme Court practice. Indeed, from the time it was
handed down until the end of the 2005 term, Chevron was applied in only
8.3 percent of Supreme Court cases evaluating agency statutory
interpretations. During this time frame, the Court employed a continuum
of deference regimes, to wit:
• Curtiss-Wright
Super-Deference, the super-deference afforded to executive
interpretations involving foreign affairs and national security;
• Seminole Rock Strong Deference, a strong form of deference afforded to agency interpretations of their own regulations;
•
Chevron Deference, the famous two-step approach that permits reasonable
agency interpretations so long as the statute has not clearly spoken to
the issue;
• Beth Israel Deference, pre-Chevron tests, associated
with particular subject areas, permitting reasonable agency
interpretations that are consistent with the statute;
• Skidmore Deference, giving agency interpretations respect proportional to their power to persuade;
•
Consultative (Skidmore-Lite) Deference, where the Court, without
invoking a named deference regime, relies on some input from the agency
(e.g. amicus briefs, interpretive rules or guidance, or manuals) and
uses that input to guide its reasoning and decision-making process; and
• Anti-Deference, which invokes a presumption against the agency
interpretation in criminal cases and in some cases in which the agency
interpretation raises serious constitutional concerns.
This
continuum is more complicated than the literature or the Court's own
opinions suggest, and it is a continuum in which Chevron plays a
modest, perhaps even minor, role. Skidmore, the New Deal decision many
thought had been rendered obsolete by Chevron, not only survives but
flourishes; indeed, Skidmore is the unexpected star of the “Chevron
Revolution.” However, Eskridge and Baer also caution that in the
majority of cases - 53.6 percent of them - the Court does not apply any
deference regime at all. Instead it relies on ad hoc judicial reasoning
of the sort that typifies the Court's methodology in regular statutory
interpretation cases.
Second, the study demonstrates that the
Court applies none of these deference regimes in a doctrinally
consistent or predictable manner. According to the data, the Court
usually does not apply Chevron to cases that are, according to the
Court's own criteria, Chevron-eligible. Analyzing how Chevron is
applied in the cases where it is invoked by the Court, Eskridge and
Baer find little doctrinal consistency, except for the proposition that
legislative history is relevant in the Court's determinations whether
Congress has delegated lawmaking authority to an agency or has directly
addressed the issue in the statute. According the data, the Court is
more likely to cite and follow Chevron in Chevron-eligible cases when
it agrees with the agency interpretation, a finding we also made for
the Curtiss-Wright, Seminole Rock, Beth Israel, and Skidmore deference
categories. Apart from that regularity, the Court's explicit invocation
of a particular deference regime is hard to predict.
Third,
although there is little doctrinal consistency, the Court's practice
does reveal regularities in cases where there is an agency
interpretation. Although noting that the Solicitor General wins most of
his cases before the Court whatever the criterion, Eskridge and Baer
report that the likelihood of the Justices' agreeing (for whatever
reason) with an agency interpretation are particularly high when:
(1)
the statutory subject matter involves the instrumental solution to
technical economic or scientific problems by an expert technocratic
agency (e.g., bankruptcy, intellectual property, pensions,
telecommunications), as opposed to social or economic legislation
involving issues the Justices believe to be more normative or political
(e.g., civil rights, entitlements, labor relations);
(2)
pursuant to congressional delegation, the agency has adopted a
legislative rule through a notice-and-comment process, and especially
if the agency is interpreting its own established rule;
(3) the agency has consistently adhered to its interpretation over time.
Ironically,
these factors – comparative expertise, open process, and consistency –
are those associated with Skidmore, but they show up in the Chevron
cases as well. Eskridge and Baer also report a significant correlation,
for all the current Justices, between voting patterns and ideology,
with conservative agency interpretations generating more support from
Justices appointed by conservative Republican Presidents and liberal
agency interpretations generating more support from Justices appointed
by moderate Democratic and Republican Presidents.
In a
lengthy normative part, Eskridge and Baer weigh in on the deference
debates within and outside the Court, especially as they relate to the
contours of the (perhaps misnamed) Chevron Revolution. Again, three
conclusions deserve to be highlighted.
First, Eskridge and
Baer join those scholars and judges who believe that Chevron is a
proper approach, so long as the agency is acting pursuant to a
congressional delegation of lawmaking authority. They support this
conclusion by reference to constitutional and statutory sources, as
well as functional considerations that have dominated judicial and
academic arguments seeking to expand Chevron's domain. Eskridge and
Baer, however, maintain that the Court's chaotic application of Chevron
needs to be addressed, if for not other reason than to provide better
guidance for lower courts. Specifically, they urge the Court to clarify
which statutes the Justices believe constitute congressional delegation
of lawmaking authority, to jettison most of the pre-Chevron deference
regimes that have survived Chevron. Like barnacles on a rusting ship,
most of these regimes (specifically, Curtiss-Wright, Seminole Rock, and
Beth Israel) should be scraped away.
Second, Eskridge and
Baer support the notion that Skidmore survives Chevron and, indeed,
would carry that thesis further. Skidmore is, and should be, the
universal default approach: any statutory issue as to which the agency
is not acting pursuant to delegated lawmaking authority is one where
the Supreme Court (and of course lower courts) ought to be receptive to
agency inputs – not just previous interpretations, but also valuable
agency-generated information about the history of the statute and of
administrative activity, factual materials about the social and
enforcement context, and analysis of the policy consequences of
different interpretations. This suggestion is by no means
revolutionary; it reflects the deep practice of the Court, which for
institutional reasons relies and perhaps has little choice but to rely
on agency inputs. The primary concern, according to Eskridge and Baer,
is that the Solicitor General is, for these institutional reasons,
playing too much a role in bankruptcy etc. cases; to prevent policy
from becoming unbalanced, the Court should consider a greater diversity
of policy views.
Third, and most important, Eskridge and
Baer's study concludes that both the practice and the theory of
statutory interpretation must view the enterprise through the lens of
the modern administrative state. Such a lens requires rethinking such
judicial doctrines as the plain meaning rule, purposive interpretation,
legislative history, stare decisis, and the substantive canons of
statutory construction. For one example, traditional theories justify
consultation of legislative history as evidence of Congress's original
intent, including compromises; critics claim that such history is
unreliable at best, corrupting at worst. Eskridge and Baer's
examination of 1014 Supreme Court cases, and the government's briefs in
most of those cases, revealed to them that, from the agency's point of
view, legislative history is more valuable as evidence of the problem
Congress was trying to solve, including values and trade-offs; the
range of discretion Congress expected the implementing agency to have;
and political feedback to the agency as it adopted various policies and
strategies. This last value, dismissed by doctrinalists as bootless
“subsequent legislative history,” is revealed dramatically in many of
the Chevron or Skidmore cases handed down by a doctrinally conservative
Court. Eskridge and Baer suggest that the Justices' practice is sounder
than the abstract theorizing of both judges and law professors in this
and other areas.
At some point during the Winter of
2007-2008, Eskridge and Baer will make their database available to
other researchers. (This summer, a leading legislation scholar is doing
an independent reality check of the authors' coding of a random sample
of the 1014 cases.)
Comments